Ontological Arguments: Anselm, Descartes, Plantinga.

The Ontological Argument: A Mind-Bending Journey to Prove God (Maybe?) 🀯

Alright, class! Settle down, settle down! Today, we’re diving headfirst into one of the most fascinating, frustrating, and frankly, bizarre arguments for the existence of God ever conceived: the Ontological Argument. Now, I know what you’re thinking: "Ontological? Sounds like something a Klingon would order at Starbucks!" πŸ‘½β˜•οΈ

Fear not, my aspiring philosophers! We’ll break it down, dissect it, and maybe even poke a little fun at it along the way. We’ll be exploring the contributions of three heavyweight thinkers: Anselm, Descartes, and Plantinga. Prepare for some serious mind-bending!

I. Introduction: Existence as a Predicate? Hold On, What?

The Ontological Argument, in its simplest form, attempts to prove God’s existence solely from the concept of God. That’s right, no empirical evidence, no observation of the natural world, just pure, unadulterated logic. It’s like trying to bake a cake without any ingredients, just the idea of a cake! πŸŽ‚

Think of it this way: most arguments for God’s existence (like the Cosmological or Teleological arguments) start with something in the world and try to infer God from it. The Ontological Argument flips the script. It says, "Let’s define God, and see if that definition necessitates his existence." 🧠πŸ’₯

Key Takeaway: The Ontological Argument is a purely a priori argument. It relies on reason and definition, not observation.

II. Anselm’s OG Argument: The Proslogion Power Play (11th Century)

Our journey begins with Anselm of Canterbury, a Benedictine monk who was clearly bored with chanting and decided to tackle the biggest question of all. He laid out his argument in his book, Proslogion, which, let’s be honest, sounds like a prescription medication.

Anselm’s argument goes something like this:

  1. God is "that than which nothing greater can be conceived." (Latin: aliquid quo nihil maius cogitari possit)
    • Think of it as the ultimate superlative. God is the most awesome, the most powerful, the most everything-you-could-possibly-imagine-ly being.
  2. A thing can exist in the understanding (in intellectu) or in reality (in re).
    • Think of a unicorn. You can imagine it (it exists in your understanding), but it doesn’t exist in the real world (unless you’ve got some serious explaining to do). πŸ¦„
  3. Suppose God exists only in the understanding, not in reality.
  4. Then we could conceive of a being that is greater than God – namely, a being with all the same qualities as God, but which also exists in reality.
    • Because existence in reality is better than existence only in the mind.
  5. But this is impossible, because God is defined as that than which nothing greater can be conceived.
  6. Therefore, God must exist in reality.

Anselm’s Argument Summarized (Table Form):

Step Description
1 God is the greatest conceivable being.
2 Existence in reality is greater than existence only in the mind.
3 Suppose God only exists in the mind.
4 Then we can conceive of something greater (God existing in reality).
5 This contradicts the definition of God.
6 Therefore, God exists in reality.

Think of it like this: Imagine a perfect pizza. πŸ• The idea of a perfect pizza is great, but an actual perfect pizza that you can eat is even better, right? Anselm is saying the same thing about God.

III. Gaunilo’s "Perfect Island" Objection: Beware of Imaginary Real Estate!

Almost immediately, Anselm’s argument was challenged. Gaunilo, a contemporary monk, came up with a brilliant (and hilarious) objection known as the "Perfect Island" objection.

Gaunilo argued:

  1. We can conceive of a perfect island, "that than which no greater island can be conceived." 🏝️
  2. Using Anselm’s logic, this perfect island must exist in reality, because an island that exists in reality is greater than an island that exists only in the mind.
  3. But clearly, a perfect island doesn’t necessarily exist just because we can conceive of it!

The problem: If Anselm’s argument works for God, it seems to work for anything. We can just define something as "perfect" and then magically prove its existence! Gaunilo’s objection highlights the potential absurdity of the argument.

Anselm’s Response (Sort Of):

Anselm tried to defend his argument by saying that it only applies to God, because God is a necessary being, while an island is a contingent being. In other words, God must exist, whereas an island doesn’t have to exist. This is a somewhat unsatisfying response for many. It essentially begs the question: why is God a necessary being in the first place? πŸ€”

IV. Descartes’ Version: The Triangle with a Twist (17th Century)

Fast forward a few centuries, and we encounter RenΓ© Descartes, the famous "I think, therefore I am" guy. Descartes brought his own spin to the Ontological Argument. He believed that existence is a predicate of God, just like having three sides is a predicate of a triangle.

Descartes’ Argument:

  1. We have a clear and distinct idea of God as a supremely perfect being.
  2. Perfection includes all possible perfections.
  3. Existence is a perfection.
  4. Therefore, God must exist.

The Triangle Analogy:

Descartes argued that just as it’s impossible to conceive of a triangle without three sides, it’s impossible to conceive of God without existence. Existence is part of God’s essence. πŸ“

Think of it like this: Imagine trying to draw a triangle with only two sides. It’s impossible! Descartes is saying that trying to conceive of God without existence is equally impossible.

Kant’s Critique: Existence Isn’t a Predicate! πŸ’₯

The most famous and influential critique of the Ontological Argument comes from Immanuel Kant. Kant argued that existence is not a predicate.

What does this mean?

A predicate is a property that describes something. For example, "The cat is black." "Black" is a predicate describing the cat.

Kant argued that saying "God exists" doesn’t add anything to our concept of God. It simply affirms that our concept has an instance in reality. It’s not a property of the concept itself.

Think of it like this: Saying "The $100 bill exists" doesn’t add any value to the $100 bill. It just confirms that there’s an actual $100 bill out there, not just an idea of one. πŸ’΅

Kant’s critique was devastating to the Cartesian version of the Ontological Argument. It seemed to show that the argument was fundamentally flawed.

V. Plantinga’s Modal Logic Makeover: Possible Worlds and Maximum Greatness (20th Century)

The Ontological Argument seemed dead in the water after Kant. But then, in the 20th century, along came Alvin Plantinga, a brilliant philosopher who gave the argument a modern makeover using modal logic. 🀯

What is Modal Logic?

Modal logic deals with concepts like possibility and necessity. It talks about "possible worlds" – hypothetical scenarios that could have been the case.

Plantinga’s Argument (Simplified):

  1. It is possible that there exists a maximally great being.
    • A maximally great being is one that is omnipotent, omniscient, and morally perfect in every possible world.
  2. If a maximally great being exists in some possible world, then it exists in every possible world.
    • Because if it didn’t, it wouldn’t be maximally great!
  3. Therefore, a maximally great being exists in every possible world (including the actual world).
  4. Therefore, God exists.

Plantinga’s Argument Summarized (Flowchart):

graph LR
A[Possible that a maximally great being exists] --> B{If so, it exists in all possible worlds};
B --> C{This includes the actual world};
C --> D[Therefore, God exists];

Key Concepts:

  • Possible World: A complete and consistent way the universe could have been.
  • Maximally Great Being: A being that possesses maximal excellence (omnipotence, omniscience, perfect goodness) in every possible world.
  • Modal Logic: Logic that deals with possibility and necessity.

Why is Plantinga’s Argument Different?

Plantinga doesn’t claim to prove God’s existence. Instead, he argues that it’s rational to believe in God. He says that the argument shows that the belief in God is logically coherent and doesn’t lead to any contradictions.

Objections to Plantinga’s Argument:

  • The "Great Pumpkin" Objection: Critics argue that you can use Plantinga’s logic to "prove" the existence of anything, like a maximally great Great Pumpkin! πŸŽƒ
  • The "Possibility Premise" Question: How do we know it’s possible for a maximally great being to exist in the first place?

VI. Conclusion: So, Did We Prove God? (Spoiler Alert: Maybe Not!)

The Ontological Argument remains one of the most debated and controversial arguments in philosophy. It’s a fascinating intellectual exercise that forces us to think deeply about the nature of existence, the limits of reason, and the very concept of God.

Here’s the Truth Sandwich:

  • The Ontological Argument is incredibly clever and intellectually stimulating.
  • It’s unlikely to convince anyone who doesn’t already believe in God.
  • It raises profound questions about the nature of existence and the limits of human reason.

In Conclusion:

Argument Key Figure Core Idea Major Criticism
Anselm’s Anselm God is "that than which nothing greater can be conceived," so existence must be part of God’s essence. Gaunilo’s "Perfect Island" objection; begs the question of why God is necessary.
Descartes’ Descartes Existence is a predicate of God, just like having three sides is a predicate of a triangle. Kant’s critique that existence is not a predicate.
Plantinga’s Plantinga It is possible that a maximally great being exists; if so, it exists in all possible worlds, including the actual world. "Great Pumpkin" objection; questioning the possibility premise.

So, did we prove God? Probably not. But we’ve taken a wild ride through the minds of some of history’s greatest thinkers. And that, my friends, is a victory in itself! Now, if you’ll excuse me, I’m going to go contemplate the existence of a perfect pizza. πŸ•πŸ˜‹

Comments

No comments yet. Why don’t you start the discussion?

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *